partial order of natural numbers
This can also be seen as the path category of the infinite linear graph .
Properties
Properties from the database
- is small
- is finitely cocomplete
- has binary products
- is thin
- has wide pullbacks
is skeletal
The relation is antisymmetric
Deduced properties
is locally small
Since it is small, we deduce that it is locally small.is essentially small
Since it is small, we deduce that it is essentially small.is well-powered
Since it is essentially small, we deduce that it is well-powered.is well-copowered
Since it is essentially small, we deduce that it is well-copowered.is locally essentially small
Since it is essentially small, we deduce that it is locally essentially small.has equalizers
Since it is thin, we deduce that it has equalizers.is left cancellative
Since it is thin, we deduce that it is left cancellative.has pullbacks
Since it has binary products and has equalizers, we deduce that it has pullbacks.has connected limits
Since it has wide pullbacks and has equalizers, we deduce that it has connected limits.has filtered limits
Since it has wide pullbacks, we deduce that it has filtered limits.is Cauchy complete
Since it has equalizers, we deduce that it is Cauchy complete.has sequential limits
Since it has filtered limits, we deduce that it has sequential limits.has coequalizers
Since it is thin, we deduce that it has coequalizers.is right cancellative
Since it is thin, we deduce that it is right cancellative.has finite coproducts
Since it is finitely cocomplete, we deduce that it has finite coproducts.has an initial object
Since it has finite coproducts, we deduce that it has an initial object.has binary coproducts
Since it has finite coproducts, we deduce that it has binary coproducts.has pushouts
Since it has binary coproducts and has coequalizers, we deduce that it has pushouts.is connected
Since it has an initial object, we deduce that it is connected.has a strict initial object
Since it is left cancellative and has an initial object, we deduce that it has a strict initial object.is inhabited
Since it is connected, we deduce that it is inhabited.has a cogenerator
Since it is thin and is inhabited, we deduce that it has a cogenerator.has a generator
Since it is thin and is inhabited, we deduce that it has a generator.
Non-Properties
Non-Properties from the database
- does not have countable coproducts
- is not essentially finite
Deduced Non-Properties*
is not complete
Assume for a contradiction that it is complete. Since it is essentially small and is thin and is complete, we deduce that it is cocomplete. Since it is cocomplete, we deduce that it has coproducts. Since it has coproducts, we deduce that it has countable coproducts. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have countable coproducts.is not cocomplete
Assume for a contradiction that it is cocomplete. Since it is cocomplete, we deduce that it has coproducts. Since it has coproducts, we deduce that it has countable coproducts. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have countable coproducts.is not cartesian closed
Assume for a contradiction that it is cartesian closed. Since it is cartesian closed, we deduce that it has finite products. Since it has finite products, we deduce that it has a terminal object. Since it has wide pullbacks and has a terminal object, we deduce that it is complete. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not complete.does not have zero morphisms
Assume for a contradiction that it has zero morphisms. Since it has zero morphisms and has an initial object, we deduce that it is pointed. Since it has a strict initial object and is pointed, we deduce that it is trivial. Since it is trivial, we deduce that it is essentially finite. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not essentially finite.is not preadditive
Assume for a contradiction that it is preadditive. Since it is preadditive, we deduce that it has zero morphisms. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have zero morphisms.is not additive
Assume for a contradiction that it is additive. Since it is additive, we deduce that it is preadditive. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not preadditive.is not abelian
Assume for a contradiction that it is abelian. Since it is abelian, we deduce that it is additive. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not additive.is not finitely complete
Assume for a contradiction that it is finitely complete. Since it is finitely complete, we deduce that it has finite products. Since it has finite products, we deduce that it has a terminal object. Since it has wide pullbacks and has a terminal object, we deduce that it is complete. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not complete.is not pointed
Assume for a contradiction that it is pointed. Since it is pointed, we deduce that it has zero morphisms. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have zero morphisms.is not locally finitely presentable
Assume for a contradiction that it is locally finitely presentable. Since it is locally finitely presentable, we deduce that it has exact filtered colimits. Since it has exact filtered colimits, we deduce that it is finitely complete. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not finitely complete.is not locally presentable
Assume for a contradiction that it is locally presentable. Since it is locally presentable, we deduce that it is complete. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not complete.is not locally ℵ₁-presentable
Assume for a contradiction that it is locally ℵ₁-presentable. Since it is locally ℵ₁-presentable, we deduce that it is locally presentable. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not locally presentable.is not an elementary topos
Assume for a contradiction that it is an elementary topos. Since it is an elementary topos, we deduce that it is cartesian closed. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not cartesian closed.is not a Grothendieck topos
Assume for a contradiction that it is a Grothendieck topos. Since it is a Grothendieck topos, we deduce that it is an elementary topos. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not an elementary topos.does not have a terminal object
Assume for a contradiction that it has a terminal object. Since it has wide pullbacks and has a terminal object, we deduce that it is complete. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not complete.does not have products
Assume for a contradiction that it has products. Since it has products and has equalizers, we deduce that it is complete. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not complete.does not have coproducts
Assume for a contradiction that it has coproducts. Since it has coproducts and has coequalizers, we deduce that it is cocomplete. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not cocomplete.does not have finite products
Assume for a contradiction that it has finite products. Since it has finite products and has equalizers, we deduce that it is finitely complete. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not finitely complete.does not have countable products
Assume for a contradiction that it has countable products. Since it has countable products, we deduce that it has finite products. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have finite products.does not have filtered colimits
Assume for a contradiction that it has filtered colimits. Since it has finite coproducts and has filtered colimits, we deduce that it has coproducts. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have coproducts.does not have sequential colimits
Assume for a contradiction that it has sequential colimits. Since it has finite coproducts and has sequential colimits, we deduce that it has countable coproducts. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have countable coproducts.does not have connected colimits
Assume for a contradiction that it has connected colimits. Since it has connected colimits, we deduce that it has wide pushouts. Since it has wide pushouts and has an initial object, we deduce that it is cocomplete. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not cocomplete.does not have a strict terminal object
Assume for a contradiction that it has a strict terminal object. Since it has a strict terminal object, we deduce that it has a terminal object. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have a terminal object.is not self-dual
Assume for a contradiction that it is self-dual. Since it is self-dual and is finitely cocomplete, we deduce that it is finitely complete. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not finitely complete.is not a groupoid
Assume for a contradiction that it is a groupoid. Since it is thin and is a groupoid, we deduce that it is essentially discrete. Since it is essentially discrete and is connected, we deduce that it is trivial. Since it is trivial, we deduce that it is a Grothendieck topos. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not a Grothendieck topos.is not discrete
Assume for a contradiction that it is discrete. Since it is discrete, we deduce that it is essentially discrete. Since it is essentially discrete, we deduce that it is a groupoid. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not a groupoid.is not essentially discrete
Assume for a contradiction that it is essentially discrete. Since it is essentially discrete, we deduce that it is a groupoid. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not a groupoid.is not finitary algebraic
Assume for a contradiction that it is finitary algebraic. Since it is finitary algebraic, we deduce that it is locally finitely presentable. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not locally finitely presentable.is not finite
Assume for a contradiction that it is finite. Since it is finite, we deduce that it is essentially finite. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not essentially finite.is not trivial
Assume for a contradiction that it is trivial. Since it is trivial, we deduce that it is finitary algebraic. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not finitary algebraic.does not have a subobject classifier
Assume for a contradiction that it has a subobject classifier. Since it has a subobject classifier, we deduce that it is finitely complete. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not finitely complete.is not balanced
Assume for a contradiction that it is balanced. Since it is left cancellative and is right cancellative and is balanced, we deduce that it is a groupoid. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not a groupoid.is not infinitary distributive
Assume for a contradiction that it is infinitary distributive. Since it is infinitary distributive, we deduce that it has finite products. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have finite products.is not distributive
Assume for a contradiction that it is distributive. Since it is distributive, we deduce that it has finite products. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have finite products.does not have exact filtered colimits
Assume for a contradiction that it has exact filtered colimits. Since it has exact filtered colimits, we deduce that it has filtered colimits. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have filtered colimits.is not Grothendieck abelian
Assume for a contradiction that it is Grothendieck abelian. Since it is Grothendieck abelian, we deduce that it is abelian. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not abelian.does not have disjoint finite coproducts
Assume for a contradiction that it has disjoint finite coproducts. Since it has disjoint finite coproducts and is thin, we deduce that it is trivial. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not trivial.does not have disjoint coproducts
Assume for a contradiction that it has disjoint coproducts. Since it has disjoint coproducts, we deduce that it has coproducts. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have coproducts.does not have wide pushouts
Assume for a contradiction that it has wide pushouts. Since it has wide pushouts and has coequalizers, we deduce that it has connected colimits. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have connected colimits.is not split abelian
Assume for a contradiction that it is split abelian. Since it is split abelian, we deduce that it is abelian. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not abelian.is not mono-regular
Assume for a contradiction that it is mono-regular. Since it is mono-regular, we deduce that it is balanced. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not balanced.is not epi-regular
Assume for a contradiction that it is epi-regular. Since it is epi-regular, we deduce that it is balanced. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not balanced.is not Malcev
Assume for a contradiction that it is Malcev. Since it is Malcev, we deduce that it is finitely complete. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not finitely complete.
*This also uses the deduced properties.
Unknown properties
—
Special morphisms
Isomorphisms: only the identity morphisms
This is true for every poset (regarded as a category).- Monomorphisms: every morphism
Epimorphisms: every morphism
It is a thin category.