CatDat

category of schemes

Properties

Properties from the database

Deduced properties

  • is locally essentially small
    Since it is locally small, we deduce that it is locally essentially small.
  • has finite products
    Since it is finitely complete, we deduce that it has finite products.
  • has equalizers
    Since it is finitely complete, we deduce that it has equalizers.
  • has a terminal object
    Since it has finite products, we deduce that it has a terminal object.
  • has binary products
    Since it has finite products, we deduce that it has binary products.
  • has pullbacks
    Since it has binary products and has equalizers, we deduce that it has pullbacks.
  • is connected
    Since it has a terminal object, we deduce that it is connected.
  • has coproducts
    Since it has disjoint coproducts, we deduce that it has coproducts.
  • has disjoint finite coproducts
    Since it has disjoint coproducts, we deduce that it has disjoint finite coproducts.
  • has finite coproducts
    Since it has disjoint finite coproducts, we deduce that it has finite coproducts.
  • is Cauchy complete
    Since it has equalizers, we deduce that it is Cauchy complete.
  • is distributive
    Since it is infinitary distributive, we deduce that it is distributive.
  • has a strict initial object
    Since it is distributive, we deduce that it has a strict initial object.
  • is inhabited
    Since it is connected, we deduce that it is inhabited.
  • has countable coproducts
    Since it has coproducts, we deduce that it has countable coproducts.
  • has an initial object
    Since it has finite coproducts, we deduce that it has an initial object.
  • has binary coproducts
    Since it has finite coproducts, we deduce that it has binary coproducts.

Non-Properties

Non-Properties from the database

Deduced Non-Properties*

  • is not small
    Assume for a contradiction that it is small. Since it is small, we deduce that it is essentially small. Since it is essentially small and has coproducts, we deduce that it is thin. Since it is thin, we deduce that it has coequalizers. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have coequalizers.
  • is not complete
    Assume for a contradiction that it is complete. Since it is complete, we deduce that it has products. Since it has products, we deduce that it has countable products. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have countable products.
  • is not cocomplete
    Assume for a contradiction that it is cocomplete. Since it is cocomplete, we deduce that it has coequalizers. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have coequalizers.
  • does not have zero morphisms
    Assume for a contradiction that it has zero morphisms. Since it has zero morphisms and has an initial object, we deduce that it is pointed. Since it has a strict initial object and is pointed, we deduce that it is trivial. Since it is trivial, we deduce that it is split abelian. Since it is split abelian, we deduce that it is abelian. Since it is abelian, we deduce that it is Malcev. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not Malcev.
  • is not preadditive
    Assume for a contradiction that it is preadditive. Since it is preadditive, we deduce that it has zero morphisms. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have zero morphisms.
  • is not additive
    Assume for a contradiction that it is additive. Since it is additive, we deduce that it is preadditive. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not preadditive.
  • is not abelian
    Assume for a contradiction that it is abelian. Since it is abelian, we deduce that it is additive. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not additive.
  • is not finitely cocomplete
    Assume for a contradiction that it is finitely cocomplete. Since it is finitely cocomplete, we deduce that it has coequalizers. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have coequalizers.
  • is not pointed
    Assume for a contradiction that it is pointed. Since it is pointed, we deduce that it has zero morphisms. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have zero morphisms.
  • is not locally finitely presentable
    Assume for a contradiction that it is locally finitely presentable. Since it is locally finitely presentable, we deduce that it is locally presentable. Since it is locally presentable, we deduce that it is complete. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not complete.
  • is not locally presentable
    Assume for a contradiction that it is locally presentable. Since it is locally presentable, we deduce that it is complete. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not complete.
  • is not locally ℵ₁-presentable
    Assume for a contradiction that it is locally ℵ₁-presentable. Since it is locally ℵ₁-presentable, we deduce that it is locally presentable. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not locally presentable.
  • is not an elementary topos
    Assume for a contradiction that it is an elementary topos. Since it is an elementary topos, we deduce that it is cartesian closed. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not cartesian closed.
  • is not a Grothendieck topos
    Assume for a contradiction that it is a Grothendieck topos. Since it is a Grothendieck topos, we deduce that it is an elementary topos. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not an elementary topos.
  • does not have products
    Assume for a contradiction that it has products. Since it has products and has equalizers, we deduce that it is complete. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not complete.
  • does not have filtered limits
    Assume for a contradiction that it has filtered limits. Since it has finite products and has filtered limits, we deduce that it has products. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have products.
  • does not have sequential limits
    Assume for a contradiction that it has sequential limits. Since it has finite products and has sequential limits, we deduce that it has countable products. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have countable products.
  • does not have connected limits
    Assume for a contradiction that it has connected limits. Since it has connected limits, we deduce that it has wide pullbacks. Since it has wide pullbacks and has a terminal object, we deduce that it is complete. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not complete.
  • does not have connected colimits
    Assume for a contradiction that it has connected colimits. Since it has connected colimits, we deduce that it has coequalizers. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have coequalizers.
  • is not self-dual
    Assume for a contradiction that it is self-dual. Since it is self-dual and is finitely complete, we deduce that it is finitely cocomplete. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not finitely cocomplete.
  • is not a groupoid
    Assume for a contradiction that it is a groupoid. Since it is a groupoid, we deduce that it is self-dual. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not self-dual.
  • is not essentially small
    Assume for a contradiction that it is essentially small. Since it is essentially small and has coproducts, we deduce that it is thin. Since it is thin, we deduce that it has coequalizers. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have coequalizers.
  • is not thin
    Assume for a contradiction that it is thin. Since it is thin and is finitely complete, we deduce that it is Malcev. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not Malcev.
  • is not discrete
    Assume for a contradiction that it is discrete. Since it is discrete, we deduce that it is skeletal. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not skeletal.
  • is not essentially discrete
    Assume for a contradiction that it is essentially discrete. Since it is essentially discrete, we deduce that it is thin. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not thin.
  • is not finitary algebraic
    Assume for a contradiction that it is finitary algebraic. Since it is finitary algebraic, we deduce that it is locally finitely presentable. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not locally finitely presentable.
  • is not finite
    Assume for a contradiction that it is finite. Since it is finite, we deduce that it is small. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not small.
  • is not essentially finite
    Assume for a contradiction that it is essentially finite. Since it is essentially finite and has finite products, we deduce that it is thin. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not thin.
  • does not have pushouts
    Assume for a contradiction that it has pushouts. Since it has binary coproducts and has pushouts, we deduce that it has coequalizers. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have coequalizers.
  • is not trivial
    Assume for a contradiction that it is trivial. Since it is trivial, we deduce that it is finitary algebraic. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not finitary algebraic.
  • is not Grothendieck abelian
    Assume for a contradiction that it is Grothendieck abelian. Since it is Grothendieck abelian, we deduce that it is abelian. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not abelian.
  • is not left cancellative
    Assume for a contradiction that it is left cancellative. Since it is left cancellative and has a terminal object, we deduce that it has a strict terminal object. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have a strict terminal object.
  • is not right cancellative
    Assume for a contradiction that it is right cancellative. Since it is right cancellative and has equalizers, we deduce that it is thin. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not thin.
  • does not have wide pullbacks
    Assume for a contradiction that it has wide pullbacks. Since it has wide pullbacks and has equalizers, we deduce that it has connected limits. This is a contradiction since we already know that it does not have connected limits.
  • does not have wide pushouts
    Assume for a contradiction that it has wide pushouts. Since it has wide pushouts and has an initial object, we deduce that it is cocomplete. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not cocomplete.
  • is not split abelian
    Assume for a contradiction that it is split abelian. Since it is split abelian, we deduce that it is abelian. This is a contradiction since we already know that it is not abelian.

*This also uses the deduced properties.

Unknown properties

For these properties the database currently doesn't have an answer if they are satisfied or not. Please help to complete the data!

Special morphisms

  • Isomorphisms: pairs (f,f)(f,f^{\sharp}) consisting of a homeomorphism ff and an isomorphism of sheaves ff^{\sharp}
    easy
  • Monomorphisms: cf. EGA IV, 17.2.6
  • Epimorphisms: